2008年9月21日 星期日

Encounters and Reflections: Conversations with Seth Benardete

Encounters and Reflections
Conversations with Seth Benardete
edited by Ronna Burger


An excerpt


Donald Lamb and a Paper on Don Quixote

...
Michael: So you submitted the Don Quixote paper to Lamb?
Seth: And he said, "Oh this can't be submitted, you know this can't be submitted." So I said "yes," but I never asked why it was nixed.
Robert: Do you remember what the thesis was?
Seth: It was all about how he was very careful not to test reality after it proved that he was wrong. I remember this thing about Manbrino's helmet.
Robert: What's that?
Seth: He made a helmet out of cardboard, which he then brought out in the backyard and took a sword to it, and immediately it smashed. So he then made another one, but didn't test it. He knew.
Ronna: That was the solution?
Seth: Right. The solution was never to test anything.
Ronna: So you went through the book and found all these instances...
Seth: About how he had carefully avoided reality. ..

走向古典詩學之路——相遇與反思︰與伯納德特聚談


內容簡介

top
這些年的學術生涯不僅磨礪了伯納德特的語言技巧,加深了他對古典思想的理解,而且經由與各色人等接觸——古怪的、虔誠的以及用自己獨特方式表現出復雜性的 人,形成了他對人性的認識。當然,有幸在有趣的時代生活在有趣的地方還不夠︰伴隨這些機遇的,還有伯納德特敏銳的視角和牢固的記憶力。不過最為重要的是, 他娓娓道來的各種故事是一個哲學頭腦的產物︰它們更為具體地闡明了他自己對哲學的理解——思想與不可預期之物的真實相遇。 伯納德特喜歡把思維的意象比作在沙灘上行走的過程︰沙中的腳印只留存片刻,旋即又被覆蓋,而人在渺無足跡的路途中繼續前行。他比任何人都更能夠和更願意一 度重新開始,並且似乎更容易被前面未知的路途所激勵,而不是熱衷在身後留下任何豐碑。

《相遇與反思︰與伯納德特聚談》為我們提供了機會,不僅了解到伯納德特的從學之路,也通過他看到學界中的人性百態,實在難得。



本書目錄  


中譯本前言(劉小楓)

引子
第一部分 相遇
 第一章 芝加哥大學(1948一1952,1954—1955)
 第二章 雅典、羅馬和佛羅倫薩(1952—1954)
 第三章 聖約翰大學(1955—1957)
 第四章 哈佛(1957—1960)
 第五章 布蘭代斯、紐約大學和新學院(:1960—2001)
第二部分 反思
 第六章 從模式到活力
 第七章 “不確定二分組合”
 第八章 愛欲與城邦
 第九章 哲學與科學
 第十章 基督教與古羅馬作家
原文索引 本書採取將原書索引複印 內文寫頁碼之方式


Encounters and Reflections: Conversations with Seth Benardete




翻譯問題
on Page 8 : "... 5-ei-6: We used to go to Hannover in the summer. My mother and father were given cubicles in the library. A college student would take care of my brother and me. One of them ..."

cubicles 當然不是 "有間小臥室" (p.7) 而是路父母在圖書館各有間小研究室


. on Page 52:
"... We finally got to meet Eliot at a party the Neffs had. Did I ever tell you about the apple strudel parties? ..."
2. on Page 53:
"... But he was so drunk at the apple strudel party that he-who usually kept his mouth shut-said, "Sir, Spain has saved America three times" And he began to keel ..."
apple strudel 翻譯成"蘋果點心 " ( p.59)可能不知所云 參考

strudel


一處編輯錯誤 主角發言 被當成內文
榮休 /退休(中間) 教授
p.272 注之"欽定教授"頗怪
原來是 Regius
... In 1841 he was named Regius Professor of Modern History at Oxford. In addition to several volumes of sermons, he wrote a three-volume History of Rome (1838 – 43). He was the father of Matthew Arnold and grandfather of the novelist Mrs. Humphry Ward (1851 – 1920)....
這日本這樣翻譯
Regius professor 〔英〕 欽定講座担当教授.
不過 也許不是"欽定"的
Regius professor
, an incumbent of a professorship founded by royal bounty, as in an English university.


****

SHELF LIFE; A Classicist's Starting Point: Putting Aside Interpretations


Published: February 16, 2002

Confessions of ignorance are not usually in a critic's best interest. But in this case, perhaps, an exception can be made. Ignorance, after all, is now common when confronting Greek literature. Beginning with ignorance is also an approach recommended by many of these demanding essays by Seth Benardete, a classicist at New York University, who died to relatively little notice in November. Because of his difficult and idiosyncratic interpretations, that notice is not likely to expand beyond a small group of philosophers, political scientists and classicists.

Yet testimonials are unqualified. Pierre Vidal-Naquet, the respected French historian, has proclaimed of Benardete, ''I have long believed that he deserves glory -- that of the heroes of Homer, to be precise.'' Harvey Mansfield, a political scientist at Harvard, said Benardete was ''the most learned man alive and, I venture to assert, the deepest thinker as well.'' According to several anecdotes, T. S. Eliot heaped praise on his brilliance. At a memorial program at New York University earlier this month, encomiums for the man -- who spent his career writing translations and commentary on Plato, a book on ''The Odyssey'' (''The Bow and the Lyre'') and essays on Sophocles, Euripides, and Aristotle -- were offered by philosophers and classicists, including Ronna Burger of Tulane University and Michael Davis of Sarah Lawrence College, both of whom edited the current collection.

But why the broad devotion to so specialized a scholar? Why the praise for a writer whose gnomic vocabulary about gnomic material uses phrases like ''eidetic analysis'' and ''indeterminate dyad''?

''The Argument of the Action'' provides some answers by collecting essays written throughout Benardete's career. They are so intimidating in their minute attention to Greek tragedies and Platonic dialogues that they can barely be read without following the works themselves (only some of which I have studied). The essays ornately weave allusions, analyses and images, engaging in close textual analysis while venturing unsettling hypotheses.

The first step, Benardete stressed, is indeed to approach the works as a beginner, to read, say, ''The Republic'' or ''Oedipus Tyrannus'' free from millennia of interpretations. At first, the arguments and plots might seem fairly transparent. Sophocles' most famous Oedipus play, for example, has long been regarded as a story about a man who unknowingly kills his father, the king of Thebes, and marries his mother. When he discovers the truth, he blinds himself. Such are the tragic consequences of desire and fate.

Such plays have, of course, been analyzed for their literary structure. But Benardete goes further. He looks not for unity but for peculiarity. Why does the queen apparently marry Oedipus before she knows about her husband's death? Why does the witness to Oedipus' crime contradict the known facts? We think we understand the action, but the closer we look the less seems clear. For Benardete the play forces the reader to blunder into its familiar world as unknowingly as Oedipus does in his, to engage in a detailed inquiry and to discover the unexpected.

Consider, he suggests, the great riddle of the Sphinx that Oedipus must solve to stop the plague that has come to Thebes: what walks on four legs in the morning, on two at midday and on three in the evening? Oedipus' answer is man, who first crawls as a baby, then walks upright and in old age uses a cane. That answer would seem to show him a master of the human.

But Oedipus is more like its victim. The problem in Benardete's view is that he sees only the general not the particular. His notion of the human is outlined by the Sphinx's riddle. All variation and difference is lost; even Oedipus himself, partially lame, does not fit the Sphinx's pattern. Yet he persists in focusing purely on the abstract. He becomes a tyrant, seeking to establish public order as if it could be created by formula. The play, Benardete argues, is about tragic consequences of political blindness.

In such a reading the surface is closely examined to reveal unexpected depths. This was also the approach of Benardete's mentor at the University of Chicago, Leo Strauss, a charismatic scholar. Students of Strauss, including Benardete, have had an almost cultic relationship to him. Many have also become influential conservative intellectuals -- most famously, the late Allan Bloom, author of ''The Closing of the American Mind.'' Strauss has, in fact, been attacked for conservativism: his unmitigated elitism and supposed antidemocratic temperament, which some say included the suggestion that Nazism was a product of the Enlightenment.

But this view of the Nazis -- and of Soviet Communism -- was not as bizarre as it might seem. It was held by Isaiah Berlin as well, because the ideals of the Enlightenment included the belief that reason had utopian powers and that humanity could be reconstructed under its guidance. That belief in the malleability of the human, Berlin argued, ended up leading to totalitarianism.

Strauss's dismissal of the reasoned perfectibility of society did not, as many have claimed, lead to a belief that the quest for justice should not be attempted. It did mean that any attempt to attain justice could only approach its goal by taking into account the ambiguities, unpredictability and variability of humanity. Strauss stressed the inherent difficulty of the project, not the need for its abandonment; that was one reason for his elitism.

This view does not seem far from Benardete's. Oedipus, again, is a political leader who mistakenly believes that justice can be attained and suffering relieved by the narrow application of reason and will alone. The word sphinx means binder or constrictor, Benardete argues, which is just what such a narrow view of the human will do: bind rather than liberate. That was Benardete's response to the Sphinx's riddle.

THE ARGUMENT OF THE ACTION
Essays on Greek Poetry and Philosophy
By Seth Benardete
434 pages. University of Chicago Press. $39.

沒有留言:

網誌存檔